Deck 12: Naïve Procrastination

Full screen (f)
exit full mode
Question
An infinite horizon model is an attractive way to model consumption decisions because it allows for consumption choices in any given period to interact with preferences for consumption in every other period.
Use Space or
up arrow
down arrow
to flip the card.
Question
Consider a fully additive model with one consumption good, U(ci)U\left(c_{i}\right) , where ii indexes time.
u(ci)=u(cj)iju\left(c_{i}\right)=u\left(c_{j}\right) \forall i \neq j if and only if ci=cjc_{i}=c_{j} .
Question
The full additive model does not assume exponential time discounting.
Question
Graham gets 10 units of utility from consuming an apple today, but needs 3 apples
tomorrow to achieve the same level of utility. Graham's discount factor is only 13\frac{1}{3} if he is riskneutral.
Question
The discount factor, δ\delta , is a measure of patience because it indicates how much an individual must be compensated in order to postpone utility.
Question
Consider a fully additive model with one consumption good, U(ci)U\left(c_{i}\right) , where ii indexes time. If δ<1\delta<1 then the fully additive model predicts ci<cji<jc_{i}<c_{j} \forall i<j .
Question
Exponential time discounting implies stationarity.
Question
Time preferences that do not satisfy stationarity are a form of projection bias: the individual is unable to predict how their preferences will change when they reach a future time period.
Question
Consumption smoothing implies that if the discount factor is close to 1 , then optimal consumption across time will be nearly constant.
Question
An individual with present biased preferences must be a hyperbolic discounter.
Question
Quasi-hyperbolic discounting is a two-part time discount function: one part is identical to exponential time discounting and the second part adds an additional discount to near future time periods.
Question
One behavioral feature of a naïve quasi-hyperbolic discounter is that they always plan to bear a utility cost "tomorrow" in order to reap the benefits in the "day after", but tomorrow arrives, their utility- maximizing choice is to postpone costs until the following the day.
Question
Delay-speedup asymmetry refers to the finding that individuals must be compensated more to delay consumption than they are willing to pay to speed up consumption.
Question
The absolute magnitude effect identifies that empirical discount factors are smaller when larger magnitudes of money are being considered.
Question
Hyperbolic discounting means that the function form of the discount factor changes over time.
Question
Procrastination and the hot-cold empathy gap can both result from

A) Loss aversion.
B) Risk aversion.
C) Time inconsistent preferences.
D) Overconfidence.
Question
An infinite planning horizon refers to

A) An infinite number of tasks to complete.
B) An infinite number of time periods over which to plan consumption.
C) An infinite amount of wealth.
D) An infinite number of individuals making a decision today.
Question
A fully additive model of the utility function U(c1,i,c2,i)U\left(c_{1, i}, c_{2, i}\right) , where ii indexes time and c1c_{1} and c2c_{2} are two different goods, has which features?

A) Utility is additive across ii (time).
B) Utility is additive across goods 1 and 2, but not across ii (time).
C) Utility is neither additive across goods or time.
D) Utility is additive across ii (time), but the function form may change in each time period.
Question
Consider a fully additive model with two consumption goods, U(c1,i,c2,i)U\left(c_{1, i}, c_{2, i}\right) , where ii indexes time. Suppose in the first period, i=0,U(c1,0,c2,0)=u(c1,0)+u(c2,0)i=0, U\left(c_{1,0}, c_{2,0}\right)=u\left(c_{1,0}\right)+u\left(c_{2,0}\right) and u(c1,0)u(c2,0)=k\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,0}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,0}\right)}=k , then which of the following is an assumption of the fully additive model?

A) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=2k\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=2 k
B) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=k\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=k
C) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=k2\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=k^{2}
D) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=k+2\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=k+2
Question
Let δtt\delta^{t-t^{\prime}} be the discount factor between tt and tt^{\prime} , where t>tt>t^{\prime} . Stationarity implies which of the following must be true?

A) δ200191<δ109100\delta^{200-191}<\delta^{109-100}
B) δ200191=δ110100\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{110-100}
C) δ200191>δ109100\delta^{200-191}>\delta^{109-100}
D) δ200191=δ109100\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{109-100}
Question
Lucas must make consumption decisions over three time periods, t=0,1,2t=0,1,2 . His preferences do not satisfy stationarity and he values current consumption more than future consumption. Let δ1\delta_{1} be the discount factor on consumption that is one period in the future and δ2\delta_{2} be the discount factor on consumption that is two periods into the future. Which of the following is true?

A) δ1=δ2\delta_{1}=\delta_{2}
B) δ1>δ2\delta_{1}>\delta_{2}
C) δ1=1\delta_{1}=1
D) δ1<δ2\delta_{1}<\delta_{2}
Question
Hyperbolic discounting was introduced as a solution to which violation of the fully additive model:

A) Stationarity.
B) Regret.
C) Time inconsistent preferences.
D) Loss aversion.
Question
Let δtt\delta^{t-t^{\prime}} be the discount factor between tt and tt^{\prime} , where t>tt>t^{\prime} . Naïve hyperbolic discounting implies which of the following is true?

A) δ200191<δ90\delta^{200-191}<\delta^{9-0}
B) δ200191=δ100\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{10-0}
C) δ200191>δ90\delta^{200-191}>\delta^{9-0}
D) δ200191=δ90\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{9-0}
Question
The common difference effect is:

A) A preference reversal.
B) Loss aversion.
C) Violation of transitivity.
D) Violation of stationarity.
Question
An individual's empirical discount factor and "true" discount factor coincide when the individual is

A) Risk averse only.
B) Risk neutral only.
C) Time consistent.
D) Loss Averse.
Question
The finding that individuals are willing to delay losses more than they are willing to delay gains is known as

A) The absolute magnitude effect.
B) The common difference effect.
C) Gain-loss asymmetry.
D) Prospect theory.
Question
The model presented in 12.67 and 12.68 combines hyperbolic discounting with prospect theory in order to address all of the following anomalies EXCEPT

A) The common difference effect.
B) Gain-loss asymmetry.
C) Loss aversion.
D) The absolute magnitude effect.
Question
In the model presented in 12.67 and 12.68 , which parameter addresses the common difference effect?

A) α\alpha
B) β\beta
C) v(ck)v(c \mid k)
D) tt
Question
In the model presented in 12.67 and 12.68 , which parameter addresses the gain-loss asymmetry?

A) α\alpha
B) β\beta
C) v(ck)v(c \mid k)
D) tt
Question
Equation 12.26 shows that Ψ(j,k)=(1+αk1+αj)(βα)\Psi(j, k)=\left(\frac{1+\alpha k}{1+\alpha j}\right)^{-\left(\frac{\beta}{\alpha}\right)} . Use this equation to show that Ψ(90,100)>Ψ(0,10)\Psi(90,100)>\Psi(0,10) if α0\alpha \neq 0 .
Question
Graham gets 10 units of utility from consuming an apple today, but needs 3 apples tomorrow to achieve the same level of utility. What is Graham's discount factor?
Question
One property of exponential time discounting is that when an individual is making a decision today about consumption in the future, they put very little weight on their utility in the distant future.
Find limtδt\lim _{t \rightarrow \infty} \delta^{t}
Question
The text states that equation 12.14 will always be consistent with 12.11 if δ3=δ22\delta_{3}=\delta_{2}^{2} . Why?
Unlock Deck
Sign up to unlock the cards in this deck!
Unlock Deck
Unlock Deck
1/33
auto play flashcards
Play
simple tutorial
Full screen (f)
exit full mode
Deck 12: Naïve Procrastination
1
An infinite horizon model is an attractive way to model consumption decisions because it allows for consumption choices in any given period to interact with preferences for consumption in every other period.
True
2
Consider a fully additive model with one consumption good, U(ci)U\left(c_{i}\right) , where ii indexes time.
u(ci)=u(cj)iju\left(c_{i}\right)=u\left(c_{j}\right) \forall i \neq j if and only if ci=cjc_{i}=c_{j} .
True
3
The full additive model does not assume exponential time discounting.
False
4
Graham gets 10 units of utility from consuming an apple today, but needs 3 apples
tomorrow to achieve the same level of utility. Graham's discount factor is only 13\frac{1}{3} if he is riskneutral.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
5
The discount factor, δ\delta , is a measure of patience because it indicates how much an individual must be compensated in order to postpone utility.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
6
Consider a fully additive model with one consumption good, U(ci)U\left(c_{i}\right) , where ii indexes time. If δ<1\delta<1 then the fully additive model predicts ci<cji<jc_{i}<c_{j} \forall i<j .
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
7
Exponential time discounting implies stationarity.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
8
Time preferences that do not satisfy stationarity are a form of projection bias: the individual is unable to predict how their preferences will change when they reach a future time period.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
9
Consumption smoothing implies that if the discount factor is close to 1 , then optimal consumption across time will be nearly constant.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
10
An individual with present biased preferences must be a hyperbolic discounter.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
11
Quasi-hyperbolic discounting is a two-part time discount function: one part is identical to exponential time discounting and the second part adds an additional discount to near future time periods.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
12
One behavioral feature of a naïve quasi-hyperbolic discounter is that they always plan to bear a utility cost "tomorrow" in order to reap the benefits in the "day after", but tomorrow arrives, their utility- maximizing choice is to postpone costs until the following the day.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
13
Delay-speedup asymmetry refers to the finding that individuals must be compensated more to delay consumption than they are willing to pay to speed up consumption.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
14
The absolute magnitude effect identifies that empirical discount factors are smaller when larger magnitudes of money are being considered.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
15
Hyperbolic discounting means that the function form of the discount factor changes over time.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
16
Procrastination and the hot-cold empathy gap can both result from

A) Loss aversion.
B) Risk aversion.
C) Time inconsistent preferences.
D) Overconfidence.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
17
An infinite planning horizon refers to

A) An infinite number of tasks to complete.
B) An infinite number of time periods over which to plan consumption.
C) An infinite amount of wealth.
D) An infinite number of individuals making a decision today.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
18
A fully additive model of the utility function U(c1,i,c2,i)U\left(c_{1, i}, c_{2, i}\right) , where ii indexes time and c1c_{1} and c2c_{2} are two different goods, has which features?

A) Utility is additive across ii (time).
B) Utility is additive across goods 1 and 2, but not across ii (time).
C) Utility is neither additive across goods or time.
D) Utility is additive across ii (time), but the function form may change in each time period.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
19
Consider a fully additive model with two consumption goods, U(c1,i,c2,i)U\left(c_{1, i}, c_{2, i}\right) , where ii indexes time. Suppose in the first period, i=0,U(c1,0,c2,0)=u(c1,0)+u(c2,0)i=0, U\left(c_{1,0}, c_{2,0}\right)=u\left(c_{1,0}\right)+u\left(c_{2,0}\right) and u(c1,0)u(c2,0)=k\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,0}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,0}\right)}=k , then which of the following is an assumption of the fully additive model?

A) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=2k\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=2 k
B) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=k\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=k
C) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=k2\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=k^{2}
D) u(c1,2)u(c2,2)=k+2\frac{u^{\prime}\left(c_{1,2}\right)}{u^{\prime}\left(c_{2,2}\right)}=k+2
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
20
Let δtt\delta^{t-t^{\prime}} be the discount factor between tt and tt^{\prime} , where t>tt>t^{\prime} . Stationarity implies which of the following must be true?

A) δ200191<δ109100\delta^{200-191}<\delta^{109-100}
B) δ200191=δ110100\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{110-100}
C) δ200191>δ109100\delta^{200-191}>\delta^{109-100}
D) δ200191=δ109100\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{109-100}
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
21
Lucas must make consumption decisions over three time periods, t=0,1,2t=0,1,2 . His preferences do not satisfy stationarity and he values current consumption more than future consumption. Let δ1\delta_{1} be the discount factor on consumption that is one period in the future and δ2\delta_{2} be the discount factor on consumption that is two periods into the future. Which of the following is true?

A) δ1=δ2\delta_{1}=\delta_{2}
B) δ1>δ2\delta_{1}>\delta_{2}
C) δ1=1\delta_{1}=1
D) δ1<δ2\delta_{1}<\delta_{2}
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
22
Hyperbolic discounting was introduced as a solution to which violation of the fully additive model:

A) Stationarity.
B) Regret.
C) Time inconsistent preferences.
D) Loss aversion.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
23
Let δtt\delta^{t-t^{\prime}} be the discount factor between tt and tt^{\prime} , where t>tt>t^{\prime} . Naïve hyperbolic discounting implies which of the following is true?

A) δ200191<δ90\delta^{200-191}<\delta^{9-0}
B) δ200191=δ100\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{10-0}
C) δ200191>δ90\delta^{200-191}>\delta^{9-0}
D) δ200191=δ90\delta^{200-191}=\delta^{9-0}
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
24
The common difference effect is:

A) A preference reversal.
B) Loss aversion.
C) Violation of transitivity.
D) Violation of stationarity.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
25
An individual's empirical discount factor and "true" discount factor coincide when the individual is

A) Risk averse only.
B) Risk neutral only.
C) Time consistent.
D) Loss Averse.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
26
The finding that individuals are willing to delay losses more than they are willing to delay gains is known as

A) The absolute magnitude effect.
B) The common difference effect.
C) Gain-loss asymmetry.
D) Prospect theory.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
27
The model presented in 12.67 and 12.68 combines hyperbolic discounting with prospect theory in order to address all of the following anomalies EXCEPT

A) The common difference effect.
B) Gain-loss asymmetry.
C) Loss aversion.
D) The absolute magnitude effect.
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
28
In the model presented in 12.67 and 12.68 , which parameter addresses the common difference effect?

A) α\alpha
B) β\beta
C) v(ck)v(c \mid k)
D) tt
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
29
In the model presented in 12.67 and 12.68 , which parameter addresses the gain-loss asymmetry?

A) α\alpha
B) β\beta
C) v(ck)v(c \mid k)
D) tt
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
30
Equation 12.26 shows that Ψ(j,k)=(1+αk1+αj)(βα)\Psi(j, k)=\left(\frac{1+\alpha k}{1+\alpha j}\right)^{-\left(\frac{\beta}{\alpha}\right)} . Use this equation to show that Ψ(90,100)>Ψ(0,10)\Psi(90,100)>\Psi(0,10) if α0\alpha \neq 0 .
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
31
Graham gets 10 units of utility from consuming an apple today, but needs 3 apples tomorrow to achieve the same level of utility. What is Graham's discount factor?
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
32
One property of exponential time discounting is that when an individual is making a decision today about consumption in the future, they put very little weight on their utility in the distant future.
Find limtδt\lim _{t \rightarrow \infty} \delta^{t}
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
33
The text states that equation 12.14 will always be consistent with 12.11 if δ3=δ22\delta_{3}=\delta_{2}^{2} . Why?
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.
Unlock Deck
k this deck
locked card icon
Unlock Deck
Unlock for access to all 33 flashcards in this deck.